Humanitarian Intervention [presentation]

An Introduction to Legal Force

By Andrea A. Long
Andrea Long, a third-year student at Albany Law School, is the Executive Editor of the Center for Judicial Process. She is a magna cum laude graduate of the Crane School of Music at SUNY Potsdam. Andrea is a Senior Editor on the Albany Law Review, she served as Project Director of the Education Pro Bono Project, and she works year-round as a law clerk in the Office of General Counsel of New York State United Teachers. She was both the winner and Best Oral Advocate of the 2011 Domenick L. Gabrielli Appellate Advocacy Moot Court Competition. For the Fall 2012 semester, Andrea is a legal intern in the law school's Domestic Violence Prosecution Hybrid Clinic.
Andrea prepared this presentation for Professor Bonventre's seminar on International Law of War & Crime, Fall 2012. She has previously been published on ILS. (See Just War: Augustine, Aquinas, & Today, Oct. 28, 2012.)

Humanitarian intervention has become a controversial subject in international law. This presentation begins with a brief overview of humanitarian intervention and situations that often require it. The presentation then describes several different international conflicts with an analysis of the humanitarian intervention that occurred. It ends by suggesting methods for future improvements in humanitarian intervention.

(click to enlarge slides)



_____________________________
For the entire presentation, open HERE.
(It is then best to download the presentation and view it from there.)

Legacy of the Nuremberg Trials

A Pithy Contemplation

By Kristen Boyert
Kristen Boyert is a third year student at Albany Law School pursuing a certificate in International Law.  This past summer, she spent five weeks interning in Abidjan, Côte d’Ivoire researching and compiling a report on human rights issues during the 2011 post- electoral crisis for ONG Transparency Justice.  She serves as a Senior Editor for both International Law Studies and the Center for Judicial Process.
This essay was prepared for Professor Bonventre’s International Law of War and Crime Seminar, Fall 2012.


We must never forget that the record on which we judge these defendants is the record on which history will judge us tomorrow.  To pass these defendants a poisoned chalice is to put it to our own lips as well.
Justice Robert H. Jackson[1]

It is with the best intentions for repair and reconciliation that the Nuremberg Trials took place. The inception of the tribunal intended to repair the wounds so deeply inflicted upon a ravaged region, as well as aid in the prevention of further atrocities. However, the inherent inception of the Nuremberg Trials is based upon the victors, and as critics argue, the jurisdiction of the tribunal is dubious, among other issues.[2]

It is universally accepted—save for a misguided few—that actions taken by the Nazi government and Nazi officials alike rose above the horrors of war to an apex that “shocked the conscience of all civilized peoples . . . .”[3]  It also goes without saying that individuals should face the consequences of their actions. The tribunal “manifested the practicability of a fair trial of war crimes in an international tribunal . . . [and] [i]t established important precedents for the development of international law concerning the definition of certain crimes . . . .”[4]

Nevertheless, as George A. Finch and Quincy Wright discuss, the tribunal steps onto unsteady ground with this venture and opens itself to criticism.[5]  Both authors describe the notion that no country is without blame.[6]  Each has waged war and defended against it.[7]  Although the Nuremberg Trials stand as a glimmer of hope for good-intentions towards persecuting wrongdoers, it also leaves questions regarding jurisdiction and sentencing.[8]

In Côte d’Ivoire, the losing presidential candidate, Laurent Gbagbo, was released into the custody of the International Criminal Court and is currently awaiting prosecution.[9]Based on my speaking to Ivorian civilians and reading partisan newspapers, it seems that some harbor distrust towards the international court and a general fear regarding a “victor’s justice” mentality.[10]

In their eyes, the international courts, and their progenies of  Nuremberg, stand for “justice for some.”[11]  Those who lose a conflict will face the consequences of justice, while those who win inevitably continue to act with impunity and are guarded by the laurels of victory.  This continues to hinder the reconciliation process and foster continued violence.

Currently, South African Archbishop Desmond Tutu is calling for Tony Blair and George W. Bush to face the consequences of their actions for the Iraq war at the International Criminal Court.[12]  Tutu cites the fictitious justification of weapons of mass destruction in order to invade Iraq.[13]

As Finch discusses, “[w]ar itself is the ultimate legal procedure against disturbers of the international peace, and from time immemorial nations have taken summary action against enemies who have fallen into their hands and who are not punishable according to law.”[14]  Although it is an imperfect system, it is still a system.  Sometimes the threat of consequences will keep people from actions rising to the level witnessed in Nazi occupied territory.

As Sir Thomas More wrote: “What you cannot turn to good, you must at least make as little bad as you can.”[15]  This is the purpose of Nuremberg and its legacy.  Perhaps not to exact perfect justice, but to implement a “justice” nonetheless.


[1] Justice Robert H. Jackson, Opening Statement at Nuremberg Trials, (Nov. 21, 1945), available at http://www.pbs.org/wnet/supremecourt/personality/sources_document12.html.
[2] E.g., Kevin R. Chaney, Pitfalls and Imperatives: Applying the Lessons of Nuremberg to the Yugoslav War Crimes Trials, 14 Dick. J. Int'l L. 57 (1995)
[3] George A. Finch, , The Nuremberg Trial and International Law, 41 Am. J. Int’l L. 20, 22 (1947).
[4] Quincy Write, The Law of the Nuremberg Trial,41 Am. J. Int’l L. 38, 42 (1947).
[5] See supra notes 3-4.
[6] Id.
[7] Id.
[8] See Write, supra note 4, at 43 (author states that critics “fall into two classes:” ones who object to the decisions and sentences; and those who view the Tribunal as having no jurisdiction under international law and applying ex post facto law); see also Finch, supra note 3 (author reviews the same criticisms in his article).
[9] World Report 2012: Côte d’Ivoire, Human Rights Watch, available at www.hrw.org/world-report-2012/c-te-d-ivoire (last visited 27 JUL 2012); Country Reports on Human Rights Practices for 2011: Côte d’Ivoire, Bureau of Democracy, Human Rights and Labor, U.S. Department of State, http://www.state.gov/j/drl/rls/hrrpt/humanrightsreport/index.htm?dlid=186187, available at http://www.state.gov/documents/organization/186399.pdf (last visited 5 SEP 2012);  Ivory Coast pro-Laurent Gbagbo General Dogbo Ble on Trial, BBC.co.UK, Oct. 2, 2012, available at  http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-africa-19797488(last visited Oct. 4th, 2012).
[10] Albany Law School, Boyert ’13 Tackles Judicial Transparency in Cote d’Ivoire, Student Spotlight, available at http://www.albanylaw.edu/students/spotlight/Pages/Boyert-%2713-Tackles-Judicial-Transparency-in-Cote-d%27Ivoire.aspx[author spent five weeks in Abidjan, Cote d’Ivoire during her summer 2012 break to intern with Transparency Justice and wrote a report on human rights violations].
[11] Id.
[12] CNN Wire Staff, Desmond Tutu says Blair, Bush should be 'made to answer' for Iraq, cnn.com, Sep. 3, 2012, available at http://edition.cnn.com/2012/09/02/world/europe/desmond-tutu-oped/index.html?hpt=iaf_c2(last visited Oct. 4, 2012).
[13] Id.
[14] Finch, supra note 3, at 34.

NATO’s Operation Unified Protector: France’s Goals Realized


By Chelsea A. Cerutti
Chelsea Cerutti, a 2012 graduate of Albany Law School, was the Managing Editor of the Albany Law Review. She did her undergraduate work at the University of Massachusetts, Amherst. She is currently a Court Attorney at New York’s highest court, the Court of Appeals.
Ms. Ceritti wrote this paper for Professor Harrington’s course on International Organizations, Fall 2011.

Over forty-four years after the French Republic’s withdrawal from the North Atlantic Treaty Organization (“NATO”), the country’s blurred and unclear relationship with the organization became clear as France rejoined the military alliance and established its presence as a military leader.  Over two years after announcing France’s intention to re-integrate into NATO’s military structure, French President Nicolas Sarkozy stepped up to help lead the first NATO operation to reach a conclusion.

The NATO operation, known as Operation Unified Protector, resulted in the end of the persecution of Libyan civilians at the hands of the Qadhafi regime.  Beyond representing a victory over those opposed to “principles of democracy, individual liberty and the rule of law,” the operational success of Unified Protector represents a subtle shift to a more equalized sharing of power between the U.S. and NATO’s European member states.

Such a shift may signify the future of NATO and its members’ security and defense policies; a shift arguably needed for the continued sustainability of the transatlantic alliance.

This paper, NATO’s Operation Unified Protector: France’s Goals Realized as US-European Defense Relations Shift, sets out to discuss France’s role within Operation Unified Protector in light of its recent re-integration into NATO’s military command after decades of participating only as a partial member.  Part II outlines an abbreviated history of the circumstances surrounding France’s partial withdrawal from NATO and the resounding military policy that guided France into the mid-1990s.

Part III discusses France’s “flexible” relationship with NATO’s military command structure during the 90s, while Part IV discusses France’s full re-integration into NATO. Finally, Part V discusses France’s role in NATO’s Operation Unified Protector in Libya, arguing that the mission represents the positive direction in which NATO is heading and ultimately suggests that merely years after rejoining NATO, France is making strides towards achieving its goal of shared European defense responsibility and power.
_____________________________
To read the paper, open HERE.

Introduction to the Just War Tradition

By Michelle K. Mallette
Micky Mallette, a third-year student at Albany Law School, is the student Executive Director of the Center. She is a graduate of the United States Military Academy, where she studied law and systems engineering. Currently, Micky serves as the Executive Editor for State Constitutional Commentary for the Albany Law Review.
Prior to law school, she worked for Procter & Gamble as a Marketing Purchases Manager and Technical Engineer. During law school, she has worked as a legal intern at the Third Judicial Department Town & Village Courts and at the Appellate Division, Third Department, and as a summer associate at Couch White, LLP.
Micky's essay is the third in the series on Just War prepared for the International Law of War & Crime Seminar, Fall 2012.

The just war doctrine is driven by two key principles, jus ad bellum—the criteria necessary to establish just cause in declaring war—and jus in bello—the limitations imposed on a party’s conduct while engaged in the act of war.[1] Together these two principles form the foundation in determining whether a State’s resort to aggression complies with international law.[2]

According to Coverdale there are four conditions that must be met in order to classify a war as just: just cause, lawful authority, proportionality, and necessity (or “last resort”).[3] Much of the discussion surrounding these conditions focuses on just cause due to competing theories involving the legality of preemptive self-defense.[4]

Whereas in medieval times justifications for war included “defense against attack, recovering something wrongfully taken, and punishment of evil,” many modern scholars only recognize self-defense as a legitimate cause for aggression.[5] Consequently, determining what qualifies as just cause in declaring war is a hotly debated topic among just war theorists.[6]
Article 51 of the UN Charter provides an exception to the prohibition on the use of force when responding to “an armed attack.”[7] Thus, scholars advocating for a strict interpretation of this provision—restrictionists—argue that resort to force can never be justified unless a State is reacting to an actual armed attack.[8]

The competing viewpoint argues for acceptance of the right to preemptive self-defense. This proposition holds that a State may anticipate an armed attack when “the necessity of that self-defense is instant, overwhelming, and leaving no choice of means, and no moment for deliberation.”[9]

Recently, some States have advocated broadening preemption even further to include attacks aimed at preventing "'rogue' States from acquiring nuclear, biological or chemical weapons of mass destruction."[10]While restrictionists are willing to concede that preemption may be necessary in rare circumstances, they strongly reject and criticize broadening preemption to include preventative measures.[11]

Use of force, they argue, can never be justified on the basis that some form of violence might occur in the distant future.[12]Rather, it is only permissible to initiate armed conflict if force is necessary to repel an imminent attack.[13]International law, however, leaves unanswered what the standards for imminence are.[14]

In the event that resort to armed conflict qualifies as just, there are still limitations on what measures may be taken by a State while engaged in that conflict.[15] Within jus in bello there are two core restrictions that guide the use of force: proportionality and discrimination.[16]

The concept of discrimination prohibits State actors from targeting noncombatants—those not directly participating in hostilities—while proportionality requires a balancing test such that any loss of civilian life or property is not excessive when compared with the anticipated military advantage to be gained.[17]

Similar to the principles of jus ad bellum, divergent theories exist surrounding the restrictions of jus in bello as well. For example, the doctrine of military necessity recognizes that “the imperative of winning the war or the battle may justify attacks on legitimate military targets despite their consequences for civilians and civilian objects.”[18]

One theorist suggests that “supreme emergencies,” such as the occupation of Western Europe by Nazi Germany, encourage States to engage in unjust means to secure victory.[19] But not all scholars agree that military necessity can ever justify “collateral damage” of civilians.[20]

“Moral absolutists treat civilian immunity as a flat prohibition”—the direct targeting of civilians can never be justified, no matter the circumstances.[21] Consequentialists on the other hand, believe that discrimination is only one factor in assessing the justification for conducting war, and as such, directly targeting civilians may be morally appropriate in dire circumstances.[22]

Coverdale contends that these theoretical differences in the just war doctrine are not problematic. The issue is a complex one, requiring “a set of questions to guide us in making prudential judgments,” rather than providing a simplistic formula to follow in assessing the just nature of armed conflict.[23] According to him, the lack of answers is not “a valid criticism of the just war tradition.”[24]

As it stands, however, the estimation of whether a war is “just” is entirely dependent upon which side of the dichotomy a theorist falls. Hence, a war may be considered just and unjust at the same time.[25]

This disparity undercuts the main component of international law— offering guidance and precedent for lawfully engaging in armed conflict.[26] Without clear answers to guide States’ action, unjust wars will continue to be waged in the future.
_____________________________
[1] John F. Coverdale, An Introduction to the Just War Tradition, 16 Pace Int’l L. Rev. 221, 223 (2004).

[2] See id. at 223–24.

[3] Id. at 229.

[4] Id. at 242–48.

[5] Id. at 230–31.

[6] Id. at 229.

[7] Id. at 232–33.

[8] John-Alex Romano, Combating Terrorism and Weapons of Mass Destruction: Reviving the Doctrine of a State of Necessity, 87 Geo. L. J. 1023, 1035 (1999).

[9] Joshua Raines, Osama, Augustine, and Assassination: The Just War Doctrine and Targeted Killings, 12 Transnat’l L. & Contemporary Problems 217, 237–38 (2002).

[10] Coverdale, supra note 1, at 244–45.

[11] Id. at 247.

[12] Id. at 242–43.

[13] Id. at 243.

[14] Id. at 248.

[15] Id. at 260.

[16] Id. at 260–61.

[17] See id. at 261, 268.

[18] Id. at 272.

[19] Id. at 274–75.

[20] Id. at 275.

[21] Id. at 277.

[22] Id.

[23] Id.

[24] Id.

[25] Id. at 276–77.

[26] See Jakob Kellenberger, Sixty Years of the Geneva Conventions: Learning from the Past to Better Face the Future (Aug. 12, 2009), http://www.icrc.org/eng/resources/documents/statement/geneva-conventions-statement-president-120809.htm.