Labels

14th Amendment 2nd Amendment Aarhus Convention Affordable Care Act Africa African Union and Reintegration programs) Animal Rights Annan_Kofi Aquinas_Thomas Archives and Web Resources Asia ASLH Asylum Augustine Ban Ki-moon Blackwater Blockade Bloggers Blood Diamonds Bosnia Cambodia Central African Republic Child Abduction Child Labor Child Soldiers Children's Rights China's One Child Policy Choice of Court Convention Cicero CISG (Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods) Citizenship Civil War Civilization Clean Air Act Cochabamba Colonialism Comparative Legal History Conferences and Calls for Papers Congo Constitutional studies Convention on the Rights of the Child Cote d'Ivoire Côte d’Ivoire Crime and Criminal Law Crimes Against Humanity Criminal Procedure Cuba Currency Manipulation Cybercrime Darfur DDR (Disarmament Demobilization Democratic Republic of Congo Disability Doha Declaration Emissions Standards Empire Energy Subsidies English legal history Environmental Law Ethnic Cleansing Ethnicity Europe European Financial Stability Facility (EFSF) European Stability Mechanism (ESM) European Union Fellowships Grants Honors and Awards FIFA (Fédération Internationale de Football Association); Extra Territorial Jurisdiction Food_Access to Foreign Judgments France Free Trade Agreements Fundamental Breach Doctrine Gaza Blockade Gender Gender Based Violence Gender Equity and Equality Geneva Conventions Genocide GMOs Guantanamo Bay Hamas Health law History of Science History of Technology HIV Human Rights Human Trafficking Humanitarian Intervention ILS Staff Immigration and Citizenship Immigration Law Import Sanctions India Education India Stock Exchange Indian Law Intellectual Property Intellectual Property Rights Internally Displaced Person (IDP) International Business International Court of Justice (ICJ) International Criminal Court International Criminal Law International Labor Organization International Labour Organization (ILO) International Law and Foreign Affairs International Sale of Goods International Whaling Commission Interpol Islam Israel Jackson_Robert H. Jus Ad Bellum; Jus In Bello Just Compensation Just War Kenya Kosovo Latin America Law and literature Law and Society Law of the Sea Convention Lebanon Lectures Workshops and Announcements Legal education Legitimacy Libya Low Emissions Zones MCX-SX Mercenaries military Mission Montevideo Convention National Sovereignty NATO Nazi Germany Necessity Non-State Actors Nuremberg Trials Operation Unified Protector Organization of African Unity (OAU) Organization of American States Originalism and the Founding Period Pacifism Palestine Peace of Westphalia Pharmaceutical Industry Piracy Policing Poverty Prisons Private Military Security Contractors (PMSC) Prize Cases Property Proportionality Prostitution Rape Realism Refugee Convention Refugees Reproductive Rights Responsibility to Protect (R2P) Rohingya Rwanda San Remo Manual Scholarship -- Articles and essays Scholarship -- Books Scottish National Party (SNP) Scottish Secession Security Council Sex Trafficking Sexuality Slavery Social media Somalia South Staff State Owned Enterprises (SOE) Sudan Syria Takings Teaching Tokyo Trials Torture TPP (Trans-Pacific Partnership) Trade Imbalance Trafficking Victims Protection Act (TVPA) Transatlantic Trade and Investment Partnership Transnational Corporations Tribal Lands Tribunal Fmr Yugoslavia Tribunal on Cyberspace Tribunal Rwanda TRIPS (Trade Related Aspects of Intellectual Property) U.N. Peacekeeping Operations U.S. Domestic Law U.S. International Law UCC; Perfect Tender Rule Uganda UN Article 2(4) UN Charter UN Counter-Terrorism Strategy UN Girls’ Education Initiative (UNGEI) UN Panel Report UN Peacekeepers UN Recognition Unfair Trade Practices UNHCR United Nations Use of Force Vienna Convention on Consular Relations; Medellin v. Texas Wartime Decision-making Water Supply Whaling World Trade Organization (WTO) Zimbabwe

Just War Influence

By Nick Gargano
Nick Gargano is a third year student at Albany Law School. He graduated from Long Island University (C.W. Post) with a B.A. in History concentrating in military air and sea power.
Prior to law school, Nick worked in concert production touring around the world with well-known musical groups for 15 years thus, expanding his love for history and igniting his interest in working in the field of international law.
This essay was prepared for Professor Bonventre's Fall 2014 International Law of War and Crime Seminar. 



Despite having history and good foundation, the “just war” theory is open-ended. Early Christian thinker Augustine suggested that a “just war” is waged in order to “preserve or to achieve peace,”[1] while another Christian thinker, Thomas Aquinas, suggested that “the advancement of good or the avoidance of evil” was the principle justification for war.[2]

Although Christian thinkers proposed the just war tradition, it may be argued that the pagan military and its warriors abided by a code that originally influenced the “just war” theory when it came to humanitarian law. Here, it is suggested that Christian thinkers used the “just war” theory to justify Christians having the same morale of the pre-Christian pagans in reference to acts of war, as pre-Christian Rome prohibited war unless “just.” However, as Rome became formally Christian, the pacifist Christian culture had to adapt to being part of a military state.[3]

Despite the “just war” theory’s broadness, there are basic principles agreed upon within international law. John F. Coverdale[4] suggested that the basic premises are: (1) the conditions that can justify the recourse to war, internationally known as jus ad bellum; and (2) the limitations on the methods that may justly be used in waging war, known as jus in bello.[5]

By virtue of the jus ad bellum, the aspects of just cause are a declaration by a lawful authority, proportionality between the goals sought and the costs, and that war is a last resort.[6] During medieval times, three causes were recognized that justified a use of force: defense against an attack; recovery of something wrongfully taken; and the punishment of evil.[7] Further, it has been argued that the conditions that justify the decision to declare war or an “armed response” are found in the United Nations Charter (UN Charter or the Charter).[8] However, the Articles within the Charter pertaining to war justification are vague and history has yet to clearly define such justification.

Article 51 of the UN Charter “recognizes the inherent right of individual or collective self-defense if an armed attack occurs against a member of the United Nations.”[9] Armed response in self-defense is lawful if four conditions are met: (1) an actual armed attack has occurred or is occurring; (2) the response is aimed at the armed attacker or those responsible for the attacks; (3) the response has the purpose of preventing future attacks; and (4) the response is necessary to remove the threat and is proportional to the circumstances.[10]

Article 51 of the Charter contains the phrase “if an armed attack occurs,” which can be interpreted to mean that an armed attack had already occurred.[11] However, it would be irrational to suggest that a state must first be a victim of an armed attack, or have knowledge of an attack coming, before taking an action in self-defense.[12] In the wake of the attacks of September 11, 2001,[13] in two resolutions, the United Nations Security Council (UNSC), which is given the tasks of deciding what constitutes an armed attack or an act of aggression, referred to the right to resort to self-defense.[14]

As such, it is obvious that the United States sustained an attack, and there clearly was no other choice in making this determination when it came to Article 51 of the UN Charter.[15] On the contrary, when Israeli jets bombed a nuclear reactor under construction in Iraq in 1981, despite the threat to Israel of nuclear weapons under the leadership of the aggressive Saddam Hussein regime, the UNSC concluded this attack to be a violation of the UN Charter and the norms of international conduct.[16] This leaves a vague area of what constitutes an armed attack.

Proportionality is a primary aspect of the concept of jus in bello—the just conduct of war—and suggests “how war may be waged justly . . . .”[17] The idea of proportionality requires “only minimum force consistent with the aim being used.”[18] This requires trying to achieve the objective of the just cause with the “least destruction possible for all concerned.”[19]

In general, “just war theorists require armies to accept some increased risk to themselves in order to reduce the number of civilian casualties.”[20] Coverdale suggests that proportionality “requires asking whether the immediate objective being sought is sufficiently important to justify tactics that will cause a given amount of death and destruction.”[21] Therefore, proportionality can provide a guide to decision-making and certain actions so the state involved is not brought up on violations of international humanitarian law.

International humanitarian law seeks to regulate many aspects that deal with proportionality, such as how to treat prisoners of war, civilian immunization from the conflict, and indiscriminate attacks. When it comes to the principle of discrimination, “once the discrimination [distinguishing between civilians and combatants] has been applied . . . if the action applied has been violated there is no room to ask whether the evil effects it produces outweighs its good effects.”[22]

The purpose of “just war” is to put some form of order or morality in times of turmoil where pacifism or diplomacy is not going to work. Although the early Christian thinkers set the groundwork of when there is a just cause to wage war, it was still subject to some negative critique as this was a new way of thinking for Christians—Pagan critics blamed the Christian influence when Rome was “sacked by the Visigoths in A.D. 410” because it was the more experienced pagan military that had set down a code of war for over 1500 years.[23]
__________________________________________

[1] Jean Bethke Elshtain, The Just War Tradition and Natural Law, 28 Fordham Int’l L.J. 742, 751 (2005).


[2] Joseph C. Sweeney, The Just War Ethic in International Law, 27 Fordham Int’l L.J. 1865, 1869–70 (2003).


[3] Robert L. Holmes, On War and Morality 117 (1989).


[4] John F. Coverdale is a Professor of Law that specializes in the interplay of law and catholic social thought. Faculty, Seton Hall L., http://law.shu.edu/Faculty/fulltime_faculty/John-Coverdale.cfm (last visited 11/23/2014).


[5] John F. Coverdale, An Introduction To The Just War Tradition, 16 Pace Int’l L. Rev. 221, 223 (2004).


[6] Id. at 229.


[7] Id.


[8] Ved P. Nanda, Law in the War on International Terrorism 81 (2005).


[9] Coverdale, supra note 5, at 233.


[10] Nanda, supra note 7, at 81.


[11] Id. at 82.


[12] Id.


[13] Members of the Al Qaeda terrorist group hijacked passenger airlines within the United States and used the planes as explosive devices to bring about the destruction of the twin towers in New York City and the Pentagon in the District of Columbia. The fact that this terrorist action amounted to an armed attack laid the foundation for self- defense, pursuant to Article 51 of the U.N. Charter. Yoram Dinstein, War Aggression And Self-Defence 228, 228 (Cambridge University Press 5th ed., 2012).


[14] Id.


[15] Nanda, supra note 7, at 82.


[16] Id.


[17] Coverdale, supra note 5, at 269.


[18] Id.


[19] Id.


[20] Id.


[21] Id.


[22] Id.


[23] Holmes, supra note 3, at 117.

0 Response to "Just War Influence"

Post a Comment